....When
we look for modernism in the movies, we find not one but at least two
forms of expression embodying two different views of experience. I shall
call one idealist and the other pragmatic.
Visionary forms of possession
The idealist tradition takes
its name from the importance it attaches to mental eventsbeginning
with acts of seeing. Hitchcock's post-war work is only the most extended
illustration of the importance of looking and being looked at in this
kind of filmmaking. In the most important scenes in Psycho, Rear
Window, North by Northwest and Vertigo, characters interact
with the world almost entirely in terms of acts of seeing and being seen.
To say the obvious, visionary events matter so much in these films because
they are not merely optical. Vision in the optical sense is a way of representing
vision in the imaginative. Seeing is a metaphor for thinking deeply, feeling
intensely, or entering into an especially intimate relationship with something.
Over and over again in these films (and especially their endings), acts
of seeing are used to represent states of spiritual, emotional, or intellectual
insight or communion.
Hitchcock employs a three-shot
sequence in his American work that illustrates the almost inveterate translation
from the one form of vision to the other. The first shot in the sequence
generally shows a silent character looking at something; the second shows
what the character sees; and the third returns to the character to show
him or her thinking, feeling, wondering about, or otherwise reacting to
what he has just seen. I call it the Look-See-Think or Feel
sequence, and it is one of the basic building blocks of idealist film
syntax. My first set of illustrations presents two examples from Psycho.
The power of the gaze
Vision is incredibly powerful
in these works. We see that most clearly in thriller and mystery films,
where the act of seeing something is endowed with ominous, negative powers.
In Silence of the Lambs, Halloween, Nightmare on Elm
Street, or Blue Velvet, vision becomes a form of spiritual
predation or imaginative control. Even in art films like The Trial
or 2001, to be watched by Hal (or someone else) is to be controlled
by the power of the gaze. To be seen, especially when one is unaware of
it, is to risk being possessed by the seer or having your
identity altered.
Notwithstanding his reputation
as the inventor of the slasher genre, in Hitchcock's work acts of seeing
are more hazardous to his characters' health than knivesespecially if
the character is seen in a private or unguarded moment. Glances are predatory.
They steal your soul. In Psycho, Marion Crane is threatened by
everyone who looks intently at her when she doesn't expect to be looked
atby her boss, by the state trooper who spies her sleeping in her car,
by the used car salesman, by Norman Bates (whose spying on her through
a hole in the wall is tantamount to sexually violating her), and ultimately
by the viewer, whose looking at her in her most private moments might
be said to collaborate with Norman in doing her in.
Indeed, one strand in the plot
of films of this sort involves the requirement that the main character
get power back by seizing control of the gaze. If he would be successful,
the character must move from being secretly looked at by others, to putting
him or herself in a position to look at them. In Hitchcock's work, Roger
Thornhill, threatened by being seen by unseen adversaries, triumphs over
them by finally being able to spy on them while remaining unseen. Marion
Crane has her privacy violated by Norman Bates' gaze, but her narrative
alter ego, her sister Lila, regains control by bringing her own
(and the viewer's) gaze to bear on Norman's inner sanctum.
Visionary community
Visionary relationships are
not necessarily threatening, however. As my second group of illustrations,
two sequences from Casablanca, demonstrates, visionary relationships
may be socially integrative and emotionally supportive. I have reproduced
two sequences: in the first, Viktor, Berger, Strasser, Renault, Ilsa,
and Sam are knitted together in a cross-stitched mesh of silent glances
shortly after Viktor and Ilsa arrive at Rick's place; in the second, Rick
intervenes to have Jan win at roulette, and Jan's wife, the croupier,
Renault, and Carl the waiter briefly form a visionary society of shared
feelings and reactions. The acts of looking in these two scenes are clearly
quite different in emotional import from those in thrillers or mysteries.
One of the signs of the difference is that in threatening works (2001,
Psycho, North by Northwest), glances tend to be unreciprocated, while
in socially supportive works (like Casablanca) they tend to be
reciprocated. That is to say, while in Hitchcock vision is almost always
a one-way streeta gun shot fired by a more powerful character at
a weaker onein Curtiz glances allow movement in both directionsmore
like the back and forth exchanges in a tennis match between equals. They
weave the characters into a fabric of interdependent and mutually reinforcing
relationships. Rather than being threatened, the characters accrue power
and their actions accrue resonance by being imaginatively enlarged. In
Casablanca, no one is ever really alone. Everyone is part of a
visionary community. It is as if the figures were immersed up to their
eyeballs in a pond, so that the smallest thought or feeling instantly
sends ripples to every other character, whose answering ripple radiates
back to the initial character. (However, it should be noted that even
in Casablanca socially integrative glances are occasionally interrupted
by predatory ones. As my illustrations indicate, Ilsa, Viktor,
Sam, Berger's, or other characters' mutually supportive glances are intercut
with Renault or Strasser's more threatening looks and reactions.)
Unmediated expression
It is not hard to understand
the appeal of visionary conceptions of experience. These works offer their
characters a stunning access of power (and allow viewers vicariously to
participate in it). Characters can rise above the limitations of space
and timethe space and time required for two people actually to interact
with one another physically, socially, and verballyand communicate more
or less telepathically. In Casablanca figures project their thoughts
into each others' consciousnesses with the speed of a glance. They turn
themselves into radio antennas, transmitting and receiving ideas and emotions
at the speed of light. Hitchcock's characters thrillingly function as
disembodied eyeballszipping lethal or supportive laser beam looks across
vast reaches of space, zapping their adversaries or making connections
with their allies.
These films figure an almost
unimaginable dream of expressive ease and power. Because visionary expression
is unmediated, it has a purity and clarity that actual spoken words, tones
of voice, gestures, and movements never can. Characters' expressions of
themselves are freed from the corruptions of personality, the indirections
of ulteriority, and the confusions of imperfect self-awareness. Characters
and viewers not only have access to each others' hearts and minds with
an intimacy that social interactions never provide, but express themselves
to each other (and to a viewer) with a purity that is never attainable
in verbal or physical interaction.
Looks speak more clearly in
these films than speech ever could. In North by Northwest Roger
Thornhill is able to read the intentions and plans of the people in the
house on top of Mount Rushmore merely by looking at them through a window
for a few minutes; in Rear Window L. B. Jeffries is able
to see into the secret recesses of his neighbors' lives by staring across
the courtyard at them; in Casablanca characters plumb the depths
of each others' souls with a glance. No verbal or physical language could
be spoken or understood this clearly and rapidly, or at such distances.
Words, tones of voice, and bodily expressions can never function this
perfectly, especially between figures who otherwise know so little about
each other and are so different from each other. Only a disembodied, mental
language can constitute such an ideal medium of exchange.
Visionary effects speak what
words cannot
In idealist works, stylistic
effects frequently pick up the expressive burden that words and social
interactions don't carry. The final scene of Casablanca (reproduced
in my third set of illustrations) demonstrates the extent to which stylistic
effects do not illustrate the dialogue and social interactions,
but substitute for it. As Rick, Ilsa, and Viktor say their farewells
on the tarmac, the style tells the story much more vividly, powerfully,
and completely than the rather banal lines of dialogue do. Rick, Ilsa,
and Lazlo are largely exonerated from having to do or say anything, while
a dazzling display of stylistic effects speaks for them.
The social expressiveness of the scene is minimized: Ilsa, Rick, and Lazlo
stand almost completely still; their costumes are nondescript; their facial
expressions are almost blank; and their verbal exchanges are minimal.
Meanwhile, the moment is overflowing with stylistic expressiveness: a
rapid succession of tight close-ups, high-key lighting, brisk editing
rhythms, emotionally charged musical orchestrations, rhetorical camera
movements (dollying and panning movements), and a few dramatic sound effects
(the sound of the propellers and the beeping of Strasser's automobile
horn). The expressiveness of the music, sound effects, and images is far
greater than anything the characters say or do.
This doublenessthe diminishment
of the social realm and enhancement of the imaginativeis crucial to
the effect of idealist works. The viewer is plunged into a world of stylistically
intense, nonverbal, nonphysical expression. No lines of dialogue could
possibly communicate this intensely, this rapidly, this perfectly. Through
these stylistic effects, it is as if we are watching Rick, Ilsa, and Viktor
communicating mind to mind, heart to heart, soul to soul, as if consciousness
could be transfusedthoughts and feelings unproblematically poured from
one character's mind into another'sand into the viewer's mind. The effect
is as exciting to watch as it is for the characters to live. Ilsa and
the others wear their hearts on their sleeves in the form of the words
and stylistic effects that bring them to us. It is as if viewers were
granted emotional and mental X-ray vision, able to see deep into their
souls and minds, able to watch streams of awareness flowing between them,
currents of feeling surging from one to the other. It is as near as narrative
film can come to putting pure states of consciousness on screen.
Moving the world into the mind
Since characters interact with
their surroundings and with each other at important dramatic moments almost
entirely in this imaginative way, idealist works implicitly downplay practical
action and social expression. In the key scenes of idealist films, characters
need to do or say or otherwise physically express almost nothing. They
need only think, feel, and see. Hitchcock's characters
are never more alive than when they are functioning in this visionary
way. They live in their imaginations, their feelings, and their thoughts
much more vividly than in their words or actions, which is why the scenes
involving their social interactions are perfunctory and boring in comparison
with those in which they are seeing.
The understanding of both experience
and identity subtly shift. These films implicitly tell us that experience
is inside us. They imply that the most important way to encounter
reality is to think about it, feel it, commune with it, understand it.
One's relation to experience becomes mental. Characters' chief expressions
of themselves and their relationships with each other are mental. They
are defined almost completely in terms of their internal statestheir
ideas, moods, wishes, dreams, intentions, and goals. They are their
states of subjectivity. To feel something, to know something, to intend
something is to be it in these films. In a visionary universe,
to have good intentions is to be spared the difficulty of having to translate
them into complex social expressions. Eventfulness moves inward, out of
the world and into the mind. Subjectivity is these works' subject.
These films endorse Isabel
Archer's ideal that you are your consciousness. (I don't know if
I succeed in expressing myself, but I know that nothing else expresses
me. Nothing that belongs to me is any measure of me; everything's on the
contrary, a limit, a barrier, and a perfectly arbitrary one.) That
is why, although the equivalents of Madame Merle and Gilbert Osmond (i.e.
characters who are masters of non-visionary forms of expression) may appear
in the course of these narratives, they are invariably placed
in limiting ways. Another way to put it is to say that even though idealist
works may use their plots to criticize characters' attempts to live their
ideals (by punishing them in one way or anotheras Isabel herself is
narratively punished by James), their styles implicitly endorse their
characters' attempts to escape the prison house of language, history,
and social interaction (just as James' verbal style endorses Isabel's
imaginative style). In Casablanca, although Ilsa may ultimately
be denied her romantic merging with Rick by the demands of the narrative,
the visual style endorses her romantic ideal more energetically than the
plot denies her its consummation.
Silence, secrets, solipsism
One consequence of this devaluation
of external expressions and actions is the social marginalization of the
characters. Thrillers and mysteries present the most extreme illustration
of the phenomenon. Hitchcock's films, for example, repeatedly imagine
his characters' most meaningful and intense experiences as taking place
when they are silent and alone: L. B. Jeffries sitting alone looking through
his camera lens, Lila Crane prowling through the Bates mansion, Roger
Thornhill looking into the windows of the mansion on Mount Rushmore, Scotty
Ferguson pursuing Judy/Madeline off in the distance. In fact, one might
say that the real horror in Hitchcock's work has less to do
with physical danger, than with the horrifying isolation of his characters.
Each of his figures serves a life sentence in solitary confinement, locked
in an individual cell of incommunicable private consciousness. Their most
important feelings and experiences can almost never be spoken or shared.
Even Casablanca, a film overflowing with crowds of characters,
without a single scene in which a character is ever physically alone,
imagines its characters to be wrapped in incommunicable states of private
subjectivity. At every point in the film, the most important experiences
and understandings of the main characters are and must remain secret and
unexpressed. Ilsa and Rick keep their past relationship and their private
meetings at Rick's place secret from Viktor; Rick keeps his continuing
love for Ilsa and his ultimate plan for her departure secret from her;
Viktor keeps his suspicions about both of them to himself. As in nineteenth-century
melodrama (from which this form of cinematic modernism descends), the
deepest truths are unspeakable.
A contradiction
Given the realistic narrative
conventions of American film, there is an artistic contradiction at the
heart of the visionary project. As much as filmmakers like Hitchcock and
Curtiz are committed to the presentation of states of subjectivity, they
must do it within the accepted forms of realistic, story-telling, narrative
presentation. The result is that virtually all mainstream American films
(which are almost entirely all part of the idealist tradition) make a
metaphoric move in which putatively objective narrative events (social
interactions, lines of dialogue, actions) are employed to represent subjective
states. The narrative magicians who make these works must pull subjective
rabbits out of objective hats. It's not an easy trick to performand
many films don't quite manage it. They fail in their attempt to use external
events and actions to evoke internal states. Shelley could simply hail
his skylark; he didn't have to come up with lines of dialogue for it to
speak or actions for it to act out. It is not at all uncommon to
find films like Apocalypse Now or The Shining uneasily see-sawing
back and forth between social and imaginative forms of presentationawkwardly
alternating between scenes that are intended to represent states of consciousness,
and scenes of social interaction that are meant to keep the narrative
moving along.
Hitchcock's work frequently
shows signs of a complete schism between the two forms of expression.
Because of his commitment to conventional narrative forms, he can't altogether
avoid having his characters engage in a certain number of practical social
and verbal interactions, but it is clear that he is unable to bring anything
like the same degree of interest and inventiveness to those scenes that
he does to his depictions of subjectivity. As an illustration, virtually
all of the scenes in Psycho in which characters interact socially
at any length are mind-numbingly dull and uninspired, evenas the film's
final psychiatric explanation illustratesto the point of being embarrassing.
The most common way realistic
narratives redirect the viewers attention away from external events and
back toward states of consciousness is simply to have characters say
their thoughts and feelings. Films like Hannah and Her Sisters,
Marty, The Bachelor Party, From Here to Eternity,
The Best Years of Our Lives, The Grapes of Wrath, To
Kill a Mockingbird, Tomorrow, and Come Back Little Sheba
may seem different from works like Psycho, Casablanca, Citizen
Kane, and 2001 insofar as they have minimal recourse to any
of the specific forms of stylistic heightening that I have focused on
as transmitters of subjectivity (emotionally freighted silent looks, exchanges
of glances, key-lighted close-ups, rapid cutting, emotionally charged
musical orchestrations), but they make up for the absence of visionary
stylistics by having characters insistently and repeatedly state (or otherwise
indicate) what they are thinking and feeling. Their key scenes consist
of characters' extended verbal presentations of their wishes, dreams,
thoughts, goals, motivations, intentions, and beliefs. Almost all of their
important dialogue passages consist of statements of subjectivity (I/you/he/she/theyÖ
want/think/believe/feel/know thatÖ etc.). The verbal expressions
in these films perform exactly the same function as the looks, visions,
and stylistic effects in the other sort of film.
It should not be surprising
that, like the visual effects in the more obviously visionary films, the
verbal expressions in these works provide direct and unmediated access
to characters' consciousnesses. Characters' words function as more or
less pure displays of subjectivityas if a figure simply, unproblematically
is the thoughts and feelings he expresses. That may not sound remarkable,
but I would note that it is almost never the case with verbal expressions
in novels, short stories, plays, or lifewhere in the first place, meanings,
thoughts, and feelings almost never exist in a pure state, and in the
second, words almost never provide unproblematic access to them. Words
in Pinter, Shakespeare, and Chekhov are never free from the obliquity,
ulteriority, and imperfection of all other human expressions of meaning.
Another way films committed
to realistic narrative forms present states of consciousness is simply
through actions and events. When Lila Crane prowls around the Bates mansion,
she doesn't need to say anything for us to follow her feelings virtually
second by second. When Rick shoots Strasser, his action speaks his thoughts
and feelings as clearly as words would. A Schwarzenegger or Steven Segal
film doesn't need to use tight close-ups or expressive lighting to allow
a viewer to follow the main character's every flicker of feeling. Consciousness
is written on the screen in capital letters with every lunge or juke.
Inner weather
In short, whether it is brought
into existence by means of looks and visions, heightened visual effects,
musical orchestrations, close-ups of faces, lines of dialogue, or mere
action, the true subject of these works is thoughts and feelings. The
defining event is the presentation of states of consciousness in their
characters and the cultivation of empathetic states of consciousness in
their viewers.
The driving scene in Psycho
(reproduced in my fourth set of frame enlargements) provides an unusually
clear illustration of how idealist film transforms putatively realistic
events into expressions of consciousness. The nominal events are as follows:
Early in the film, Marion Crane steals money from the real estate office
in which she works and flees in her car to rendezvous with her lover.
On the final leg of her flight, she drives throughout one entire day and
on into the night. As it gets darker, it starts to rain. The storm intensifies
and her windshield gets increasingly harder to see through. She blinks
and winces as the headlights of oncoming cars glare into her eyes. By
the end of the scene, it is late at night, and Marion, lost and uncertain
where she can go to get out of the storm, turns off on a side road and
pulls into the parking lot of the Bates Motel. It would be an unimaginative
viewer, however, who did not realize that the worldly events are not really
the point of the scene. As even a student in Film 101 realizes, Hitchcock
systematically and comprehensively transforms the driving, the rain, and
the night into representations of subjectivity. The storminess figures
a storm of feeling within Marion. The buildup of external disturbance
communicates a crescendo of emotional disturbance. The scene is less about
geographical disorientation than imaginative lostness, less about outer
than inner weather. (Hitchcock makes us so accustomed to the inveterately
metaphorical presentation that we don't bat an eye when the storm suddenly
subsides after Marion arrives at the Bates Motel. When she is calm, by
definition the world is calm.)
In strong idealist works (of
which Hitchcock's films are virtuosic examples) virtually every action
and event is inflected to carry imaginative meanings that redirect our
attention away from the physical surfaces of life and into depths of consciousness.
Films in the idealist line make this particular metaphoric move repeatedly.
Under the guise of presenting the world, they give us the mind.
Dream films
The most general manifestation
of this process is the symbolic mode of presentation that most American
art films employ. Virtually every visual and acoustic event in works otherwise
as different from one another as Citizen Kane, The Trial,
Vertigo, North by Northwest, 2001, Heaven's Gate,
Apocalypse Now, Blade Runner, and Pulp Fiction functions
quasi-allegorically. Almost nothing is merely its poor, paltry, realistic
self. Every experience is shifted one notch to the side in order to bear
a larger, more imaginatively resonant meaning. Take the opening of Citizen
Kane for instance. Even the most naive viewer knows that the lugubrious
music on the soundtrack, the languorous camera movements and dissolves,
the shadowy lighting, the chain link fence, the No Trespassing
sign, the dilapidated grounds, the lonely mansion, the dying words of
the man in the bed all function metaphorically. Welles is not presenting
a real fence or sign or mansion, but images of desolation, wastage, loss,
isolation, loneliness, self-destruction.
The symbolic technique imparts
the dream-like quality to many of the best known works in the American
cinematic tradition. Objects and events are relentlessly abstracted: in
Psycho everything from the storm Marion Crane drives through, to
the Bates mansion (which does not function as a real house at all, but
as an imaginative repository of middle-class taboos and repressions connected
with smothering mother-love, incest, homosexuality, masturbation, insanity,
and murder), to small details like Lila's discovery of a recording of
Beethoven's Eroica Symphony, which Hitchcock can count on
his viewers treating not as a real object (in which case it would be meaningless),
but as a symbolic one (having some punning connection with eroticism.)
So highly esteemed is the symbolic
method in American art film that it is frequently treated as being synonymous
with cinematic seriousness. It is taken for granted that this is what
important or artistic films do. Symbolic methods
are valued because they offer a stunning enlargement of meaningfulness.
The imaginative enrichments that the Romantic poets felt they had to confine
to the realm of reverie and vision are imagined to be present in everyday
life. They move off the page and into the world.
Symbolic modes of presentation
also flatter us because they affirm the importance of individual consciousness.
These films imagine a universe sympathetic with and responsive to our
feelingsas if the pathetic fallacy were no longer a fallacy. The universe
resonates to Charles Foster Kane's pulse beat. When Marion Crane is upset,
it storms. When Rick, Viktor, and Ilsa are emotionally revved, airplane
propellers rev up; when they are anxious, Strasser's horn beeps; when
Ilsa's heart pounds, cannons fire.
The merging of perspectives
The process I am describing
is a double one: Works within the visionary/ideal/symbolic tradition (the
most complete designation of the branch of cinematic modernism I am describing)
don't merely shift their characters into distinctively imaginative ways
of processing experience, they shift their viewers along with them. Viewers
enter into the same visionary relation to experience that the characters
in these films enter into. These films not only depict meditative states;
they use music, silences, and close-ups of faces and objects to evoke
corresponding meditative states in the viewer. When characters see the
world in a visionary way, the viewer enters into a visionary relationship
with what is on screen. When a character thinks or feels, the viewer thinks
or feels along with him or her in the cinematic equivalent of mental telepathy.
Marion Crane ponders stealing an envelope full of money, worries about
getting caught by her boss, or wonders what is in the house on the hill;
the viewer ponders, worries, or wonders along with her. When Lila Crane
entertains imaginative or emotional understandings of objects and events,
the viewer does. We become mind readers moving through a world of mind
reading characters. When Ilsa feels something, the viewer feels similar
emotions along with her. When the characters in Casablanca mind-read
or jump through space in a room, the viewer does with them.
The most obvious illustration
of the blending of imaginative points of view that I am describing is
the so-called identification process by which the main characters in these
works become mental and emotional surrogates for the viewer. Identification
is fostered by two devices in idealist films. The first is optical: point-of-view
photographic and editing conventions encourage the viewer to see
through the eyes of the characters and, to some extent, to experience
things the same way they do. The second is psychological: the personalities
of the characters are kept fairly bland and nonspecific in order to facilitate
empathy. Characters' identities are kept loose and baggy enough so that
almost any viewer can easily to slip into their skins. (Any prickly particularity
or spiky strangeness might create a rub or a catch that would prevent
frictionless emotional inhabitation.)
Consider Psycho's Lila
Crane. Because her character is so generic, nothing gets in the way of
a viewer becoming herso that as she prowls through the Bates
mansion the viewer goes step by step with her, not only optically seeing
through her eyes (so that when she jumps at her reflection in the mirror,
we jump with her), but seeing things in the same way she does.
She attempts to decipher the meanings hidden in the objects in the Bates
bedroom and nursery; we attempt to decipher them along with her. She is
puzzled by certain objects; we are puzzled. She experiences insights;
we experience them along with her, experiencing things in the same abstractly
metaphoric way she does.
American vision
These films positively insist
that the viewer and major characters move from optically seeing someone
or something to visionarily seeing its imaginative significance.
The work of art and life is to dive beneath the surface, to convert matter
into spirit. Merely to see something (in the optical sense) is to be in
a superficial and almost always deluded relationship with it; to understand
it, we must see it. For both characters and viewers, vision
must be translated into Vision; perception must become perception. The
process of converting sight into insight is enacted over and over again
by characters in visionary works. What is the plot of Psycho, after
all, but the efforts of various figuresMarion, Arbogast, Sam, and Lila,
one after the otherto pressure objects and events at the Bates Motel
and mansion to yield their deep meaning, their visionary
significance? And what is Hitchcock's style but a parallel effort to entice
the viewer to collaborate in pressuring reality in the same way? Hitchcock's
mystifications tease both characters and viewers into looking beneath
the surfaces of life, encouraging them to move from the physical to the
metaphysical.
The move is necessary because,
in this understanding of life, material appearances are trivial or misleading,
while imaginative depths are profound and revealing. Surfaces betray;
social and physical expressions are always, at least potentially, unreliable.
Truth is not a property of accidental, worldly phenomena, but an essence
somewhere beyond the phenomenal universe. It resides in a realm of pure
thought and feeling somewhere outside the impure world of objects and
social expressions.
Films in the visionary/ideal/symbolic
tradition enact one of the master narratives of American artwhat Melville's
Ahab called pierce[ing] through the mask. The makers of these
films (and the viewers who participate in these films' quests) take their
place in a long line of deep divers in American cultureextending from
Edwards, Hawthorne, and Melville to the Lowell, Barthelme, and Pynchon
more recently. The world is a repository of spiritual and emotional meanings
that must be decoded. The actual perceptual world is meaningless or chaotic
until we penetrate its mysteries. The symbolic/allegorical style of these
films is based on the belief in the possibility of a sacramental, restorative
vision. Character and viewer alike are offered the prospect of seeing
beneath the random, causal surfaces of life into a realm of coherence
and meaningfulness.
With its Puritan origins, it
should not be surprising that pain is usually associated with this effort.
One must suffer to redeem reality. The conversion of sight into insight
requires self-sacrifice and purgation. The effort involved in piercing
through the mask is the plot of all of Hitchcock's late films. Dial
M for Murder, Rear Window, Vertigo, North by Northwest,
and Psycho each begin by having characters (L. B. Jeffries,
Roger Thornhill, Scotty Ferguson, Arbogast, Lila Crane) and viewers see
things which they can't understand. Vision (in the optical sense) is abundantly
and easily available from the start, while vision (in the imaginative
sense) is baffled. Only after extensive narrative work is performed and
suffering undergone is the long-deferred imaginative breakthrough granted.
I would go one step further
and argue that the conversion process enacted by Hitchcock's detectives
or Welles' reporterthe ferreting out of secrets and the discovering
of hidden imaginative significanceshas become the model for American
film criticism itself. Essential truth is located within or behind accidental,
phenomenal reality. The critic's job is to dive beneath the surface, to
find the sermon in the stone, to move from the profane to the sacred.
As much as the viewers of these films and the characters in them, the
critic explicating them pursues a sacramental vision.
The loss of the world
It is only because of the pervasiveness
of these forms of understanding that we overlook their cost. Such expansions
of our powers do not occur without corresponding shrinkages. The visionary/ideal/symbolic
tradition figures at least five related losses.
The loss of sensory and bodily
reality
Where one's identity is so
largely imaginative, life becomes an out-of-body experience. Insofar as
characters in these works look their relationships into being, read each
others' minds and project their thoughts and desires more or less telepathically,
they might as well be brains in vats communicating by video monitor. Their
identities and interactions are almost entirely dephysicalized. Like Marion
Crane driving down the road in Psycho, they go up into a steam
of thought and feeling. Casablanca's Ilsa and Viktor and Psycho's
Marion and Lila do not really have physical identities. Can anyone even
remember how they move, hold their bodies, or gesture? They have realized
Emerson's dream of becoming transparent eyeballs, but in the
process (as he says in Emancipation in the British West Indies),
their skin and bones [have become so] transparent [they let the]
stars shine through.
That is the explanation for
one of the most paradoxical aspects of Hitchcock's work: the fact that
notwithstanding all of the apparent physical intrusiveness in his films
(the stalking, attacking, slashing, and killing), there is almost no sensation
of manual contact between his characters. Where possession is so profoundly
visionary, actual grabbing, touching, and holding are unnecessary. When
the world is carried up into the mind, its physicality and tangibilitythe
heft and rub and pinch of experienceare diminished. Where experience
is made equivalent to states of consciousness and feeling, materiality
is bled out of it. Reality is de-realized. We feel that, even before we
understand it, from the aloofness and detachment of Hitchcock's cushiony
camerawork. It puts the viewer at precisely the same distance from physical
reality that his characters themselves maintain. It frictionlessly glides
somewhere just above the real world, unsullied by it, hermetically sealed
off from contract with it, declining to dirty its hands by messily engaging
itself with it.
These films are machines for
abstraction. Casablanca, Citizen Kane, Psycho, 2001,
and Blade Runner give us events, objects, and actions swollen with
imaginative significance, at the cost of an inevitable attenuation in
their concreteness. The spacemen in 2001 go on an imaginative journey,
not a realistic one. Kane's sled is a symbol of a lost childhood, not
a physical object you could get splinters from. The house in Psycho
is not a material building, but a series of nested, ever more private
imaginative spaces. Psycho's imaginative enrichments are worldly
impoverishments. (Contrast Marion Crane's meals with the meal Antonio
and Bruno eat in De Sica's Bicycle Thieves to appreciate the pervasiveness
of Hitchcock's derealizations.) Where depths are so emphasized, surfaces
are invariably diminished in importance. Where life is treated as a repository
of secrets, its outside becomes something we merely reach through.
The loss of time
The loss of the body is paralleled
by the loss of time. We see this most obviously in the speed with which
relationships between characters are established. Because their identities
are ideal, characters can attain virtually instant intimacy
on the basis of shared intentions, feelings, and ideas (or become instant
enemies on the basis of similarly abstract differences). Because identities
are mental, relationships can take place in fast forward. Marion Crane
sits down with Norman Bates and unburdens herself of her most private
feelings five minutes after they meet. He does the same to her. Arbogast
introduces himself to Sam and Lila and is their friend and partner seconds
later. Berger pledges his life to Lazlo on the basis of a glance. Where
heart speaks directly to heart and soul to soul, the time-bound awkwardness
and pudency of non-visionary relations are left behind.
The viewer does the same thing
the characters do. The meaning of people, places, and things in these
films can be read by a member of the audience more or less instantaneously.
Knowledge can be this quick (for both characters and viewers) because
it is an abstract, intellectual event. It takes place in a glance, at
a distance, intellectuallythe way we learn a fact or recognize a sound
or a color. This recognition knowledge is a special and very limited kind
of knowledge. It is knowledge defined as insight rather than acquaintanceas
knowing something rather than getting to know it.
Familiarity, extended, nuanced contact with the subject would actually
get in the way of this sort of quick knowledge.
The difference between insight
and acquaintance is the difference between having a thought
and thinking. Thought, insight, visionary knowledge is about
attaining a truth: Rosebud is an unfillable loss; Norman Bates is his
own mother; X is Y. Thinking, in contrast, is a way of functioning imaginatively
in time, an ongoing, continuing way of being in the world, a mode
of alertness, sensitivity, and engagement that can't have an end-point.
In their commitment to unearthing secrets, clues, and revelations, visionary
works define knowledge as a goal rather than a process. As a character
or a viewer, you suddenly see or know or feel
somethingor you don't. The ends of Hitchcock's moviesin which the
main character and the viewer are served up a series of explanations that
account for more or less everythingsuccinctly illustrate the stasis
of the acts of atemporal seeing that occur time after time
in visionary works.
The visual and acoustic style
of visionary works implicitly minimizes the temporality of experience.
The Strauss on the soundtrack of 2001, the kick-lighting in Blade
Runner, the elevated and depressed camera angles in Citizen Kane,
the outsized sets and short lenses in The Trial offer summary,
shorthand ways of knowing. They push the pause button on the ebb and flow
of lived experience. The viewer is told how to feel about some aspect
of the character or his situation once and for all. We get
these truths (about Joseph K's insignificance, Kane's megalomania, the
comical courtliness of the spaceships' docking), the way we get the punch-line
of a joke; we don't live into them the way we live with a friend, a Beethoven
symphony, or a George Eliot novel.
Such a vision of truth final,
complete, and absolute may represent a gain for eternity, but it is a
definite loss for life. Do we really want to live in a world in which
truth is something that can be seen like a piece of furniture or known
like a basketball score? Do we really want art that imagines experience
to stand still like a painting, when it is so obviously on the move like
a piece of music? As William James asks in A World of Pure Experience,
why do we expect truth to be a static relation out of time when
it practically seems so much a function of our active life? Outside
the movies, it takes time to learn things or have meaningful experiences.
It takes time for relationships to develop. It takes time for meanings
to be made. The time is not something you can just factor out without
changing the experience itself.
The loss of uniqueness
States of consciousness are
impersonal, because thoughts and feelings (at least in the shorthand terms
in which these films render them) are generic. Inner states inevitably
lack the variety of expressions. There are no fat intentions or thin intentions,
no embarrassed or glib visions, no hesitant or assertive abstractions.
Visionary forms of presentation lack the idiosyncrasy of individual expressions.
Our visions are more or less alike; it's the nonvisionary aspects of our
lives (our personalities, bodies, gestures, facial expressions, tones
of voice) that make us different. In this respect, a person's ideas, theories,
goals, motives, and philosophies are the least personal (and least unique)
things about him.
The absence of expressive particularity,
idiosyncrasy, and individuality in idealist film includes the props, costumes,
and events. In the initial romantic rendezvous between Marion and Sam
in Psycho, nothing is particularized or unique. The hotel room
might be any hotel room; the uneaten lunch might be any uneaten
lunch; the beep of a car horn outside the window might be the beep of
any car horn. Even the lover's quarrel is generic. The words and
tones are generic. The lunch-time rendezvous is generic. One might reply
that the hotel scene is a relatively unimportant one (and that hotel rooms
are pretty generic anyway), but the deindividualized nature of experience
is just as striking in subsequent scenes in Psycho: when Marion
packs her suitcase and flees with the money in her car; when she is stopped
by the policeman; when she flees in the storm; when Norman Bates spies
on her in her room; when he attacks her in the shower; when Arbogast offers
his services to Sam and Lila as a detective; when he cross-examines Norman
about whether Marion stayed at the motel; when he sneaks into the Bates
mansion; when Sam stalls Norman; when Lila prowls through the mansionit
could really be anyone absconding with any cash, any
guilty motorist stopped by a policeman, any anxious driver, any
voyeur spying on any woman, any psycho killer, any
private detective, anyone searching for clues, etc. , etc., etc..
Anyone or no one. There are no individuals in Psycho. There are
only generic events, generic responses, generic interactions.
It is not just external events
and actions that are made generic; personal experience itself is depersonalized
by idealist works. The uniqueness and individuality of characters' internal
states is denied. When one or another character looks up at the Bates
mansion from the motel, into Norman Bates' office, around Marion's motel
room, or at objects in Mrs. Bates' bedroom, there is nothing to distinguish
one act of looking, thinking, feeling, or knowing from anotherabsolutely
no difference between Marion's looks, thoughts, and feelings and Arbogast's,
Lila's, and Sam's. There is just the generic visionary act.
Actors are cattle in
this expressive universe. You wheel them in, position them, light them
in certain ways, photograph them from several different angles, lay in
some music on the soundtrack, and the job is done: generic mental states
replace unique personal expressions. As John Cassavetes said to me about
mainstream film in general: There's no behavior. The acting
in most idealist/visionary works is as schematic and generalized as a
Kuleshov experiment. Every gesture, facial expression, and tone of voice
is generic. A pantomimed indication of an emotion, an abstract
look (made meaningful by the mood music that underpins it
or the narrative events that precede and follow it) takes the place of
a distinctive personal expression. A statement of thoughts or feelings
substitutes for the presentation of something too personally unique to
be reduced to an impersonal idea.
The impersonality of the characters'
existences is driven home by their narrative interchangeability in idealist
film. In Psycho, for example, as one figure after another is bumped
off or given a new narrative assignment, the next one steps in to take
over the previous one's duties. Lila can frictionlessly fill in for Marion
and Sam for Arbogast because they are more or less indistinguishable links
in a substitutional chaingeneric narrative placeholders in clothes.
There's not even any difference between the men and the women in this
respect. At this level of abstraction, gender differences disappear. Everyman
has become so generalized that he is no longer identifiably a man.
Far from being a failure or
oversight on Hitchcock's part, it seems clear that the omission of what
Cassavetes called behavior was deliberate. As his entire oeuvre testifies,
Hitchcock was not interested in expressive uniqueness, but cultural, emotional,
and psychological archetypesgeneral, abstract, imaginative relationships
and dependencies. His films are not about what makes us different and
irreplaceable (our unique personalities and forms of expression) but what
links us with everyone else (our dreams, dreads, desires, and fears).
Schematic understandings run
throughout idealist film. Look at works otherwise as different from each
other as Citizen Kane, Sabrina, 2001, The Graduate,
Star Wars, Thelma and Louise, and Apocalypse Now.
The experiences in them have the phenomenological thinness (and ontological
generality) of an allegory or a dream. They aren't depictions of individuals
but types. The characters and situations are abstract markers for general
imaginative positions. Nothing in them is unique or unprecedented. In
fact, like all mass culture expressions, these films would risk illegibility
if their characters and situations departed too far from types. To reach
the largest possible audience, they deliberately attempt to give us everyone's
experience in general (which means they give us no one's in particular).
The loss of otherness
In downplaying expressive uniqueness,
idealist expression suppresses otherness. The loss is a significant one,
particularly if we understand otherness in its deepest meaningnot
merely connoting exposure to specific sexual, racial, or cultural differences,
but exposure to alien consciousness in any form. Otherness in this sense
offers the opportunity to know in new ways, to see and hear with new eyes
and ears, to feel new emotions, to be granted new powers, to participate
in new forms of sensitivity and awareness. Because of their generic understandings,
idealist works look in the other directiontoward an all-encompassing
sameness of point of view, feeling, and idea.
Although it's often said that
the identification process (which these works heavily rely
on) encourages the viewer to become one of the characters,
in fact the opposite is closer to what actually takes place: The viewer
forces the character or characters to become him. Rather than inhabiting
a different consciousness, the viewer makes the character over in his
own image. It's an almost inevitable side-effect of the nature of idealist
expression. Because characters are kept expressively somewhat nonspecific,
they function as Rorschach ink blots for a viewer to project his thoughts
and feelings onto, empty receptacles for a viewer to pour his feelings
into. Rather than being forced out of himself, crashing up against the
brick wall of an alien consciousness, the viewer colors the slightly blank
character in with own personal emotional and intellectual meanings.
In fact, it is precisely because
these characters (and the actors who play them) are expressively nonspecific
and open-ended that most viewers are so comfortable with them. The vagueness
allows each viewer to feel that the character is him or her. Expressive
individuality and personal particularity would only get in the way of
instant intimacy. If the character were someone, it couldn't be everyone.
Precisely because the visions in idealist film represent the point of
view of no one in particular, they can become the point of view of anyone
in general. The seer is able to drop into what is seen because no unique
individual is doing the seeing. Idealist art is committed to a fundamentally
easy and relaxed relationship between the viewer and what is viewed. But
where the chasm between self and others is bridged so easily, so rapidly,
so painlessly, genuine otherness disappears. No real learning or discovery
takes place.
Being replaces doing
Idealist/visionary works foster
a fundamentally contemplative relationship to experience. Individuals
exist to think and feel, to read thoughts and feelings in others, and
to allow their own thoughts and feelings to be read. Experience becomes
an intellectual event. Idealist film comes very close to the values of
the late-18th century British cult of sensibility where your sentiments
and intentions matter far more than anything you may or may not say
or do. Feeling and thinking substitute for doinga point which
is almost comically illustrated in Casablanca by the narrative
importance given to Ilsa's imaginative relationship with Rick as compared
with the cursory treatment of Viktor Lazlo's life and work. Notwithstanding
Rick's remarks in the final scene about how the problems of three
little people don't amount to a hill of beans in this crazy world,
the entire film is devoted to proving the opposite point: that what Rick
and Ilsa feel for each other is more important than anything Viktor
Lazlo does to save the world. (Even what Rick and Renault feel
in the final scene is clearly more important than anything they or anyone
else may do as a result of it.)
Since, as I already pointed
out, knowledge in these works is a form of insight rather than acquaintance,
it is easy for knowing to become a passive event. Knowing isn't a way
of moving through experience, but a set of facts to be discovered. Truth
is out there to be perceived, separate from yourself; it is recognized,
not made. Meaning is revealed to you; it is not something you create.
Again Hitchcock's work illustrates the point. The character is a reader
of texts whose meanings exist independently of him. The texts can be cryptic
or obvious, and one can be a better or worse reader of them, but one is
still only a reader. The conception of truth in these works is spectatorial
(to employ Dewey's term).
Watch ten minutes of Citizen
Kane, Psycho, 2001, or Blade Runner with this
in mind and the point will be clear: In both the optical and imaginative
senses, characters exist to see and be seen, and objects and events (a
recluse's dying words, a spooky house on a hill, a mysterious Monolith
on the moon) exist to be seen into. Because idealist works prefer mental
and imaginative relationships over physical interactions with experience,
experience becomes something you have rather than do. It
is about seeing things a certain way, feeling a certain way, adjusting
your angle of visionnot about actually interacting with (and therefore
affecting the meaning of) persons, places, and things. Knowledge is an
intellectual phenomenon, a series of thoughts and feelings, not a course
of practical actions and events. Truth becomes something outside yourself
that can be known, rather than a relationship between you and the world.
You don't interact with the world in ways that potentially change it and
you; you realize, understand, appreciate, feel what it already and unalterably
is. You don't make realities in this world (children, families,
personal relationships, works of art), you discover truths that
would have been there even if you had never come along.
Idealist/visionary works cultivate
spectatorial relations to experience in their viewers as much as they
reward them in their characters. When Lila Crane walks through the Bates
Mansion, the reporter searches for information in Citizen Kane,
or the astronauts try to understand the Monolith in 2001, the characters'
relationship to experience in these films is indistinguishable
from the viewers' relationship to the experiences of them. These
works depict contemplative stances in their characters and cultivate them
in their viewers. As the entire preceding discussion is intended to demonstrate,
however, when experience is taken up into the mind, we may gain our souls
but lose the world.
Embracing the world
There is an alternative expressive
tradition within American film, though, because it is a minority position,
it is far less familiar. I shall call it pragmatic modernism due to its
affinity with the philosophical writing of Ralph Waldo Emerson, F. C.
S. Schiller, William James, Oliver Wendell Holmes, and John Dewey. The
differences between the pragmatic and the visionary/idealist/symbolic
positions could not be more striking. In the idealist tradition, reality
is elsewhereunderneath or beyond the world of practical experience and
ordinary lifein an abstract, disembodied realm of feelings, thoughts,
and insights. The goal is to leave the fluxional expressive surfaces of
life behind and make contact with a clarifying mental realm.
The pragmatic artist declines
to make that move. He says that however mutable or turbulent they may
be, there are only surfaces, and that our job is (to adapt Emerson's metaphor)
to skate on them. For the pragmatic artist, in William James' paraphrase
of Chauncy Wright's formulation, behind the bare phenomenal factsÖ
there is nothing. To put it in terms of the Isabel/Merle
dialogue I earlier alluded to: In the pragmatic tradition, we are not
our invisible intentions (what we aspire to be, want to be, or feel
ourselves to be), but our actual expressions. We are not our deep ideas
and insights, but our superficial appearances (what we express ourselves
as, what we actually do). What shows is all there is. The pragmatic artist
is committed to a profound superficialityin effect agreeing with Oscar
Wilde that it's only superficial people who do not judge by appearances.
The pragmatic work calls us
back into relation with the complexities of action and expression in the
world. The consequence is a shift in the conception of what it is to be
in the worldor, to put it more precisely, a shift from understanding
experience in terms of states of being to understanding it in terms of
acts of doing. Idealist/visionary works ask characters and viewers to
see and be; pragmatic works insist that they perform their being. Visionary
filmmaking is Platonic. It values insight (depicting it in the characters
and cultivating it in the viewer); the pragmatic artist insists on the
priority of performance (what William James calls practice).
The pragmatic work tells us that it is not sufficient to encounter the
world optically and possess it imaginatively; we must negotiate it, interact
with it physically, socially, verbally. The pragmatic work tells us that
the world exists not to be seen into, not to be known mentally
but, as Dewey put it, to be undergone. Experience is not equated
with states of being, but acts of doing.
Skating the surfaces of life
But the best way to define
a form of filmmaking so opposed to states of abstraction is not abstractly
but by example. Although the pragmatic aesthetic finds its finest flowering
in the work of a number of post-war American independent filmmakers, it
is not confined to American examples. Jean Renoir's The Rules of the
Game is a particularly useful starting point because it lends itself
to comparison with Casablanca.
While Curtiz insistently moves
inward, putting his characters' thoughts and feelings on display, Renoir
holds his viewers on the outside. The Rules of the Game keeps us
in the realm of behavior, studying impenetrable (and frequently inscrutable)
surfaces. Characters in Casablanca are transparent; their words
and their film's stylistic effects let us sink a mine shaft into a subterranean
core of consciousnesses. Figures in The Rules of the Game are opaque;
we can't see into their hearts or read their minds. Intentions, good or
bad, are everything in Casablanca; they are irrelevant in The
Rules of the Game. As a line of dialogue tells us, Everyone
has good intentions [raisons]. Robert, Octave, Jurieu, and
Christine won't be reduced to their motives, goals, or ideals, because
consciousness for Renoir can never be disentangled from the forms in which
it is embodied. For Renoir, we are not our internal states, but all of
the things that express them: our behavior, tones of voice, facial expressions,
gestures, movements, manners, and styles of expression. To say the obvious,
it is not that Renoir's characters don't have ideas or feelings, but that
the pragmatic film refuses to uncouple them from the practical expressive
acts in which they manifest themselves. You can't get to consciousness
without going through expressions and, to a large extent, remaining
within them. Forms matter. Unexpressed, silent, private consciousness
(the staple of idealist film) is a fiction.
Idealist film traces experience
back to states of subjectivity for the same reason many people go through
life trying to figure out other people's motives and intentions. By reducing
the complexity of expressions to the simplicity of intentions, we clarify
what is obscure and unify what is diverse. Subjectivity represents the
possibility of transcendental, resolving understandinga way of knowing
sprung free from the contingencies of history, culture, and gender, and
the obliquity of manners and personality. It offers a foundation for understanding
that leaves behind the compromises and mixed motives of actual human expression.
(How complex and changing facial expressions and tones of voice can be;
how much simpler are intentions signaled by lighting effects or mood music
orchestrations.) But like all foundational understandings, idealist understanding
depreciates the surface experiences it underpins. When life is defined
in terms of consciousness, the parts of it that will not be reduced to
feelings, intentions, and ideas are downplayed.
Meaning is largely decoupled
from practical forms of expression in idealist works. Our understanding
of Rick's, Viktor's, Ilsa's, or Sam's words and glances is not deeply
affected by the nuances of their delivery of their lines or how they walk,
move, or gesture. In contrast, Christine, Jurieu, Robert, and Octave can
never be dissolved back into their abstract statements and sentiments.
Their expressions are mediated. Their content is contained. Everything
these characters are is inflected by their individual body types and ways
of moving (compare Robert's with Octave's), ways of dressing, vocal tones
and speech rhythms (compare Christine's with Genevieve's with Lisette's),
facial expressions, and mannerisms (compare Marceau's with Jurieu's).
Their being is inseparable from its doing. Renoir's films
are celebrations of expressive particularity, uniqueness, and idiosyncrasy,
not merely to give variety to the delivery of the lines, but because
in his conception of life these expressive differences make all the difference.
It's not an accident that when
we remember films like 2001, Blade Runner, or Apocalypse
Now, we remember a series of disembodied visions, images, or lines
of dialogue, while when we remember a film like A Woman Under the Influence,
we recall a thousand sensory details: the different shapes of the children's
bodies in their swim suits; the touching way little Maria walks up the
stairs or Mabel hops across the lawn on one foot; Dr. Zepp's greasy, owlish
appearance; the difference between Nick's vocal tones and timbres (his
orders from headquarters talking at people) and Mabel's entirely
more hesitant and vulnerable tones. For Renoir, Cassavetes, and all pragmatic
filmmakers, what you are is not separable from your body, your behavior,
your pacing, your timing, your tones of voice.
Truth in spaces, times, and
bodies
Visionary film is committed
to leaving such personal differences behind in order to ascend
into a heaven of superpersonal knowledge. Take Hitchcock as an illustration.
Although truth in his work is almost always presented as one person's
vision (usually the main character's optical and psychological point of
view), the imaginative goal is ultimately to rise above the limitation
of the character's merely personal view to attain an ideal view in which
personal differences disappear and the point of view of the main character,
the director, and the viewer merges into an objectively verifiable truth.
When Lila Crane finds out the truth about Norman Bates; when Jeff finds
out the truth about his neighbors; when Scotty finds out the truth about
Madeline; when a viewer finds out the truth about Rosebud; when the astronauts
find out whatever they do in 2001what is discovered is imagined
to be out there to be found. Knowledge is independent of the knower. Truth
transcends the trower; the thought does not need a thinker.
For the pragmatic filmmaker
there can be no view from nowhere, no understanding that is not understood.
All truth is conditional. Expressive and perspectival differences can
never be factored out. All knowledge is based in particular ways of knowing.
It is partial and contingent. Truth can never be separated from the ways
it is bought into existencein this case, the emotional colorations of
different characters' personalities. As for a portrait painter or a choreographer,
for Renoir or Cassavetes, there can be no truth outside of the specific
bodies, faces, costumes, manners, and personal styles that express it.
Personally unexpressed truthobjective, superpersonal truthis
a meaningless concept.
Multiple-mindedness
Both the magisteriality and
authoritativeness of Hitchcock's camerawork and the quest structure of
his work clearly figure the possibility of final, absolute, unitary understanding.
The camera positioning, framing, lighting, and editing represent the viewpoint
of an ideal observer capable of seeing and hearing everything that matters
in the best possible way (though in order to increase suspense he may,
of course, withhold a necessary piece of information or encourage a misunderstanding
that temporarily misleads the viewer or the main character). The style
and narrative structure lead inexorably to a revelation of a final truth.
The pragmatic aesthetic rejects
such essentialist concepts: of an ideal or correct
view; of a final truth; of a unitary understanding. In William James'
term, its world is pluralistic. There are a variety of paths through experience.
While essentialist work is implicitly single-minded and intolerant of
variety, pragmatic work is multiple-minded, believing experience is too
complex to be reducible to any one view or interpretation. Films like
The Rules of the Game, Cassavetes' Faces and A Woman
Under the Influence, and Elaine May's Mikey and Nicky are committed
to honoring as many different relations to experience, as many different
personal perspectives as possiblenone necessarily superior to any other.
There is always a right place to look and a best
way to understand things in Hitchcock, but in A Woman Under the Influence,
the spaghetti breakfast, the whistling on the bed, the homecoming gathering
around the table, and the standing on the sofa scenes force the viewer
to hold four, five, six, or more, different (and conflicting) viewpoints
in mind at once, each of which is equally valid and important. There is
no right (or wrong) way to speak or act, no best way to think or feel,
no ideal knowledge to attain. The Rules of the Game, A Woman
Under the Influence, Faces, and Mikey and Nicky don't
aspire to rise above the partiality and diversity of personal points of
view, but to maximize their importance. The goal is not to leave differences
behind, but to give them full playto appreciate as many alternative
points of view and ways of being as possible. That is why actors
(and characters) in these works are encouraged not only to look, act,
and sound as different as possible from other characters, but as different
as possible from themselves at other moments.
There are four specific stylistic
differences between The Rules of the Game and Casablanca
that contribute to these different understandings of experience. The general
heading they all fall under is that pragmatic film jettisons point-of-view
photography and the subjectivity editing convention to employ photographic
techniques that resemble documentary filmmaking.
1. The ninety-degree turn:
Insofar as idealist film is committed to making the character's thoughts
and emotions the subject of the shot, the actor's face is turned either
directly toward the camera to provide maximum visibility or directly away
from it to allow the viewer, as it were, to see through the character's
eyes. We look directly at Jack Nicholson's face and into Meryl Streep's
eyes (unless we look through them, as if we were the character). Pragmatic
works don't make faces so prominent. They frequently introduce a ninety-degree
or larger angle between the direction the character is facing and the
direction the camera faces. The character turns inward to interact with
his group, more often than not sitting, standing, moving at an angle to
the camera position.
In idealist film, the character
plays to the camera and for the viewer; in the
pragmatic film the character functions more or less independently of the
camera position, playing to, for, and with the characters around him.
The effect is radically to change the cinematic experience: The viewer
isn't inside the characters' heads, sharing their perspectives, looking
out through their eyes, but off to one side of them, looking at them,
at a certain critical distance from them. The viewer is not in
the scene living it, but outside it, overhearing it. The world exists
not as a series of feelings to be shared and minds to be inhabited, but
as a collection of bodies, voices, movements, and actions to be experienced.
Merging becomes impossible; multiple views must be maintained.
Rather than conflating the
perspective of the viewer and the character, a chasm separating the points-of-view
of the characters from that of the viewer opens. The single view of the
visionary work gives way to the genuinely plural views of the pragmatic.
Our view is no longer privileged, no longer the only right
or best view. Other views become possiblebut inaccessible, impenetrable,
unknowable ones. The character's point of view is no longer open to the
viewer, but is turned away, invisible, hidden. A mysterious imaginative
space inhabited by the character is created. Rather than being on the
inside looking out, the viewer is positioned outside of private, inward
turned events. It's the difference between a gathering of us's and
a gathering of them's. We can know idealist characters and experiences
the way we know ourselves and our own experiences. We are inside them
the way we are inside ourselves. The most we can know pragmatic characters
is the way we know someone else. We eavesdrop on a world that exists and
moves independently of us, a world that won't open itself to us, a world
that in fact veils itself from us, and resists knowing. A world of subjectivities
gives way to a world of objects. The mystery of genuine otherness
is born.
2. A preference for medium
and long shots over close-ups: The most important dramatic moments
in films of consciousness are almost always presented in terms of an extended
series of medium shots and close-ups that focus in on characters' eyes
and facial expressions. Although The Rules of the Game doesn't
eliminate close-ups, it generally employs long or medium distance photography
so that a figure's face and eyes do not command such an inordinate amount
of attention. Characters' identities expand beyond their facial expressions;
they become their entire bodies, movements, and gestures. As D.H. Lawrence
and Walt Whitman were not the first to understand, the definition of the
soul changes when your spirit is not confined to your mind but includes
your fingers and feet, actions and gestures. The soul has a body.
A second effect of favoring
medium and long shots over close-ups is that characters are not conceived
as being essentially separate from one another (as imaginative identities
necessarily are), but are understood to bring themselves into fullest
existence in their interactions with others. Even scenes in The Rules
of the Game which employ medium and tight shots of a central figure,
like the one in which Christine greets Jurieu, almost always have other
characters visible in the background or on the sides of the frame (or
are intercut with reaction shots of other characters). Identity is relational.
3. The use of open
frame spaces and loose forms of narrative presentation: As
is the case in virtually all Hollywood film, the style of Casablanca
and Psycho more or less continuously dictate the viewer's interpretation
of every shot. He is told what to look at, why he is seeing it, and given
plenty of time to figure things out. The Rules of the Game situates
the viewer in a perceptual space in which there is much more to see and
take in, less direction on where to look, and less definiteness about
what it all means. Locations, backstories, and situations are not clearly
established. Important characters are not necessarily centrally
positioned or key-lighted, but are allowed to move around within the frame
spaceor even out of it. Rather than tersely cutting from important point
to point and person to person, the camera more loosely roves around the
set, noticing events and groups of characters in different areas, not
hesitating to take in various bits of background and foreground business
that might not be strictly relevant to the main action. Experiences are
to some extent unanalyzed. They are not cut into bite-sized pieces (in
the form of close-ups) and prepared for easy consumption (with editorializing
stylistic glosses), but are kept fairly whole and unprocessed (with fill-lighting,
medium and long shots, group interactions, and nontendentious narrative
placement). Experience is served up a slightly raw or uncooked state.
Rather than having his eye directed, his focus clarified, and his interpretation
narrowed, the viewer is left a little to his own devicesat least a little
free to decide where to look around in the frame, what to pay attention
to, and what to think about it.
The pragmatic work is semantically
loose-jointed. It imagines a universe in which objects, events, characters,
and utterances have a more relaxed, less determined relation to meaning
than in the visionary worknot only less tightly tied to any one meaning,
but potentially linked to different and perhaps contradictory meanings
at the same time. It allows for the possibility of there being different
understandings of the same experience. Because it treats experience as
being semantically a little random or casual, it holds it more lightly
than the other kind of film. This goes against the grain of our habitual
ways of understanding. We want definiteness and definitiveness. Semantic
overdetermination is usually taken to be an artistic virtue. Isn't it,
after all, the greatness of Citizen Kane, that virtually
everything in itevery shot, prop, camera angle, line of dialogueemphatically
means somethingsomething even the lowliest freshman can be trained
to take in at a glance? Films like 2001, Apocalypse Now,
Blade Runner, Full Metal Jacket, Pulp Fiction, and
Fargo create worlds of intense and pervasive meaningfulness.
Even putting aside the ways
such semantic overdetermination pushes viewers around, denying interpretive
room to breathe, it's worth pondering how much of experience is left out
when it is made so semantically coherent: its casualness and adventitiousness;
its repetitions, digressions, and dead ends; its loopiness, eccentricity,
strangeness, and sheer unknowability. To borrow one of Robert Frost's
metaphors, if experience is a tent swaying in the breeze, the essentialism
of art film hammers in the pegs and pulls the guy wires so taut that it
removes the interesting wrinkles and wiggle. It takes the play out of
life. The pragmatic artist loosens the chains of causality and frustrates
or delays understanding in order to allow a little life (or what James
in Some Problems of Philosophy calls novelty) back
in.
4. Perceptions replace conceptions:
The idealist film subtly encourages a movement from perceptions to
conceptions, while the pragmatic film holds the viewer more firmly (if
somewhat bewilderingly) in the realm of the senses. The viewer is denied
an optical or imaginative guide through the film, a personal
surrogate to walk us through the experience, direct our vision, and assist
in our interpretation (either in the form of a character whose point of
view we can identify with or a director, cameraman, or editor who will
clearly establish where we are in scene after scene, show us where to
look, and suggest what it all means). The result is that we must drift
a little at sea through the visual space, letting our eyes and minds rove,
continuously adjusting our feelings and beliefs, changing our minds as
we go along. Especially given the mutability and complexity of the sensory
surface in most pragmatic works, the viewer is forced to remain on the
qui vive, surfing the leading edge of a breaking perceptual wave,
staying perceptually on the move, without being able to put down an enduring
conceptual anchor.
Due to their fairly intellectual
mode of presentation, shots in Psycho, Casablanca, and other
idealist works encourage the viewer to translate them into general psychological
points and narrative meanings. The orderliness of the visual spaces and
the clear, conceptual organization of the sequences of shots repeatedly
emphasize the presence of an underlying abstract logic. The effect is
to create a powerful impression of meaning undergirding the perceptual
surface. The viewer is ever so slightly abstracted from what is seen to
consider why it is being shown and what it means. These films induce a
distance between the viewer and what is being presented. They convey the
feeling of being about an experience rather than giving the sensation
of actually having the experience.
The pragmatic film takes away
the aboutness. To watch The Rules of the Game is to be put in the
position of uncertainly responding to a shifting, unpredictable sequence
of events not obviously underpinned by an abstract, unifying logic. To
watch Cassavetes' work is to be tossed head-first into an almost overwhelmingly
raw, unassimilated experience. These works emphatically deny intellectual
distance and control over the experiences presented. To view them is less
to learn about a group of characters and situations than to have
something resembling the kind of experiences we would have if we were
actually thrown into similar situations with similar figures. A fundamental
perceptual shift takes place: undergoing must (at least temporarily) replace
understanding. Living in space and time must take the place of
knowing outside of space and time; states of abstraction must give
way to acts of perception. In a word, thinking must give way to experiencing.
Life without intentions
Two films by Mike Leigh can
throw additional light on pragmatic understandings of experience. Bleak
Moments dramatizes the relationship of a young woman, Sylvia, with
two young men: Norman is a gawky, taciturn lodger who rents a room in
her house; Peter is a somewhat older and relatively more poised professional
who lives in her neighborhood. It is clear that both men are as hungry
for companionship and possible romance as Sylvia is, but what separates
Bleak Moments from idealist cinematic presentations is that, beyond
establishing the three characters' shared desire for companionship, Leigh
provides almost nothing in the way of access to their motives and intentions.
Sylvia's, Norman's, and Peter's thoughts, goals, plans, and desires are
neither verbalized, translated into dramatically pointed looks, nor summarized
in mood music or lighting effects.
A later Leigh work, Meantime,
does something similar in terms of another threesomethis time a triangle
involving the relationship of Mark and Colin, two brothers from a lower-class
background, and their middle-class Aunt Barbara. As in the other film,
Leigh establishes a few general dramatic tensions and inequalities: It
is clear that the brothers are in a competitive relation with each other;
and that the aunt feels sorry for one of them (Colin) and wants to help
him and to encourage him to break free from the other brother's (Mark's)
influence. But beyond these basic tensions, the film denies access to
Mark's, Colin's, and Barbara's thoughts, feelings, and desires.
The basic intellectual insights
that idealist film trades in are simply unavailable, which means that
from scene to scene, the viewer is left guessing about the direction a
personal interaction may take, what a character will say or do next, and,
above all, what precisely a character intends by what he or she says or
does at a particular moment. For viewers accustomed to Hollywood's luxurious
displays of subjectivity, the experience can be frustrating, bewildering,
or downright maddening. The experience is a little like being an outside
guest at a large family gathering where there is lots of hidden history
and unspoken emotional agendas. Clarifying, resolving, deep
understandings are unavailable; all there is are shifting, complex surfaces.
Answers to important questions are simply unavailable: Specifically, in
Bleak Moments: Is Norman romantically interested in Sylvia? Is
Sylvia offering herself to Norman? Is she offering herself to Peter, or
teasing and mocking him? In Meantime: Is Mark out to help Colin
be independent or trying to keep him under his thumb? Does Barbara have
Colin's interests at heart or her own? Are she and Mark acting selfishly
or altruistically? These are the fundamental issues the films raise, but
none of them is answered even at the end.
These questions are not answered,
not because Leigh is withholding information, but because they are fundamentally
not answerable. The reason that we aren't told what Sylvia, Peter,
Norman, Barbara, Mark, or Colin really want from each other,
what they mean when they say something, or what their fundamental
intentions are at a given moment is that they themselves
don't and can't know. Even the actors playing them, or Leigh, who
wrote, directed, and edited their performances would be able to answer
these questions. As potential lovers getting to know each other, Sylvia,
Peter, and Norman themselves really can't understand their relative positions
or know what they want from each otheror whether they want anything
at all. Given their situation, such a concept of knowing or
intending is meaningless. The very idea of such wants and
understandings is absurd. These characters don't have basic motives
or goals. They don't have plans for their relationship.
They don't have visions of what they desire or
need. They don't have secret wishes or ideals
that would clarify things if only we knew them. There is no realm of deep
feelings or unexpressed intentions to get to.
There is no substructure of essential thoughts, feelings,
and ideas that can resolve and simplify the genuine vagueness,
open-endedness, and unformulatedness of these interactionsand if there
were, these scenes would not be worth bothering with. Sylvia and Peter
feel their way toward or away from a romantic relationship step by step,
and if we are to appreciate the intricacy, sadness, and beauty of their
emotional dance it can only be in the same step-by-step way. Colin, Mark,
and Barbara play a chess game in which they can never see beyond the current
move, and the viewer must learn to function in the same move-by-move way.
The mystery of the visible
That should make it clear that
when I argue that Hitchcock and Curtiz (and other idealist filmmakers)
provide access to depthscharacters' fundamental points of view, feelings,
thoughts, and intentionsand that Renoir, Leigh, Cassavetes, May, and
other pragmatic filmmakers deny access to them, I don't mean that the
pragmatic artist is merely keeping such information from the viewer. Idealist/visionary
artists frequently withhold information about motives and intentions in
order to grab a viewer's attention or stoke up the dramatic intensity
of a scene in a way that creates an effect superficially similar to what
the pragmatic artist does. But the difference is that, even though they
may be temporarily hidden from view, the intentions and motives are still
there and eventually revealed. The pragmatic denial is more fundamental.
It is a denial that life is organized (and comprehensible) in terms of
essential states of consciousness, a denial that surface expressions are
traceable back to simpler, underpinning thoughts and feelings.
The mysteries in pragmatic
works are real, while those in Hitchcock's and Welles' work, Tarantino's
Pulp Fiction, Mamet's House of Games, or DePalma's Dressed
to Kill are fake. The mystifications in these films can ultimately
be cleared up. (We might as well be in a Sherlock Holmes story.) The mysteries
in pragmatic films never can. There is nothing to resolve, no secret to
uncover, no answer for the next scene to reveal. The mysteries in pragmatic
films are not tricks introduced to hold our interest or tease usbut
are unavoidable side-effects of the genuine complexity of the events and
characters. They aren't something added to a situation; they are just
how things are.
Leigh's Norman may seem superficially
similar to Hitchcock's; Leigh's Sylvia may seem superficially similar
to Hitchcock's Marion. Both sets of characters are fairly secretive, private,
and shy. Both seem fairly mysterious. But the difference is that in Hitchcock
the reason for the secretiveness is that the character has a secret (concealed
thoughts, desires, or actions)which is to say there is not any real
mystery at all, since once either's thoughts and fears are revealed, the
mystery disappears. The mystery in Renoir's, Leigh's, and Cassavetes'
worlds is not premised on a secret. It is not in the depths but on the
surface; not in the realm of the invisible, but the visible.
Another way to think of it
is to notice that Hitchcock generally generates mystery by giving his
characters two identitiesa public and a private one, nested inside one
another like Chinese dolls. Although the discrepancy between them creates
whatever mystery there may appear to be, there is actually no mystery
in either identity by itself. Each one is perfectly coherent, consistent,
and intelligible; the gap between them is the only source of mystification.
Leigh's characters have only one self. There is no secret identity behind
or beneath the surface one. The mystery is in the self that showswhich
is a much more complex situation. It's the same mystery we find in Chekhov's
or Faulkner's most interesting characters. Or in the title characters
in Cassavetes' Husbands (who even if we asked them couldn't tell
us what they really want or feel at any one moment). Or in Cosmo Vitelli
in Cassavetes' The Killing of a Chinese Bookie, who himself doesn't
understand his own emotional needs and desires, let alone indicate to
a viewer what they are. There is no possible resolution of the mystery
in these films.
New forms of knowledge
If these works don't simply
drive viewers out of the movie theater, demanding their money back, the
result is to induce a state of attentiveness distinctively different from
what the visionary film cultivates. Since it is impossible to dive beneath
the multivalent, shifting expressive surface to a realm of clarifying
thoughts and stable intentions, the viewer cannot coast above a scene,
but is put on the edge of his seat, noticing, listening, pondering, wondering,
speculating, and respondingwatching flickers of emotion in faces, and
ebbs and flows of gestural energy, listening to semidemiquavers in voicesfollowing
the second by second evolution of a complex interactionwithout the prospect
of an ultimate clarification. Viewers must learn to function without road
maps. They must get used to worlds with a degree of unresolvable uncertainty.
There is no summarizing, deep truth to take away from the experience;
there is only the experience itself. The deep meaning is the
process of having experiences that are not traceable back to deep meanings.
In this situation what counts
as knowledge changes. Because we cannot ground our readings of scenes
in abstract understandings, we must abandon generalities and accept particulars.
We must give up the ideal of thinking as an event in which we leave behind
the contingencies of temporal and spatial knowledge, and embrace a sense
of thinking that is spatially and temporally engaged and sensorily on
the move. We must change our understanding of understanding. To understand
the experiences the pragmatic work presentsas to understand a great
jazz performanceis not to leave the perceptual events behind in order
to reach a realm of intellectual abstraction and visionary clarity, but
to plunge into the sensory experience, synchronizing our rhythms
with its flow, sensitizing ourselves to its attributes. Pragmatic works
teach us to think in space and time, not outside of them. The search
for the essences of epistemology must be replaced by a willingness to
function within the flowing movements of history. The viewing experience
becomes less like searching for the solution to a puzzle, in order to
find out something, than a process of living within an unusually
stimulating and demanding set of experiences. There is no resolving truth
and no end point to be attained in these films. There is only a shifting
course of events to be negotiated. Our inveterate cultural and intellectual
quest for product must be replaced by a willingness to remain in process.
Truth as vision in Plato's sense is replaced by truth as conversation
in Richard Rorty's and Daniel Dennett's sense.
Characters beyond character
The idealist film is committed
to an essentialist conception not only of expression but of personal identity.
Apparent vagaries of behavior and expression are harmonized by being traced
back to a central, unifying center of selfhood. In fact, the simplicity
of its characters is one of the things that makes Hollywood film (the
most extended body of idealist cinematic work) so satisfying to most viewers.
However diverse its fundamental expressions, personal identity in these
works is ultimately revealed to be essentially simple, static, and unitary.
At the muddy bottom of the food chain, in the simplest of action pictures,
the Die Hards and Rockys, the characters are more or less
completely defined by a few practical goals (e.g. capturing the terrorists)
and personal characteristics (e.g. rugged sex appeal). In slightly more
sophisticated works like Citizen Kane and North by Northwest,
selfhood is only slightly more complex. Figures like Charles Foster Kane
and Roger Thornhill assume different personae depending on whom they are
with, are shackled with mistaken identities, and have identities that
are kept secret and not revealed to other characters or the viewer for
much of their works, but the character is ultimately revealed to have
a dominant identity that unifies the apparent diversity. That is to say,
although the character may display apparently contradictory characteristics
in the course of the film, the differences are ultimately harmonized in
a deeper understanding: Ilsa's shift from sentimentality to toughness
and Rick's shift from cynicism to commitment are revealed to be unitary
reflections of their earlier romantic relationship; Kane's kaleidoscopic
succession of moods (charm, buoyancy, swagger, braggadocio, acquisitiveness,
nastiness, superciliousness, megalomania, rage, despair, loneliness) is
resolved by being seen as the expression of a single, unfilled emotional
void. The initial heterogeneous understandings are ultimately unified
by a subsuming, final understanding. The character in effect stands stillmore
or less consistently being, acting, and uttering an unchanging essence
through-out the film, while the viewer digs deeper and deeper toward the
Rosebud that explains it all. What William James ironically wrote in Pragmatism
and Humanism about the idealist world-view might describe the idealist
psychological conception of character: We live upon the stormy surface;
but with this our anchor holds, for it grapples rocky bottom.
The pragmatic filmmaker does
not understand personal identity this way. He does not believe that our
identities are organized around a central essence, quality, intention,
or goal. He is not convinced that the heterogeneity of our experiences
and expressions necessarily reflects a central unity, and to pretend it
does is to tell a lie about them. Compare any of Cassavetes' most interesting
figures with Norman Bates, Roger Thornhill, or Scotty Ferguson for a crash
course on the difference. Though Norman (the most complex of the three)
temporarily eludes understanding, he is ultimately revealed to be quite
simple. As the psychological explanation that concludes Psycho
emphasizes, the apparent diversity of his previous expressions is ultimately
unified under the rubric of his mother complex. There is no
comparable explanatory key to the main characters in Faces, A
Woman Under the Influence, or Opening Night. As the title of
one of his films suggests, Cassavetes' protagonists function less as a
definable bundle of attributes than as tuning forks resonating within
shifting force fields of influences. The self as a fixture
is dissolved; its boundaries are made permeable; it bleeds into others
and lets others bleed into it. In fact, substantives like selfhood
are themselves too static and bounded to capture the mercuriality of these
figures' streaming identities. Chet, Jeannie, Mabel, and Myrtle are less
nouns than verbs, less entities than energies, less sets of characteristics
than shifting capacities of responsiveness.
To live through the shifts
of beats and tonal flickers in the dancing scene in Faces (in which
Richard and Freddy vie for Jeannie's affections, and in a matter of minutes
Freddy goes from being flirtatious and romantic to hostile and abusive),
or the tonal swoops, imaginative pirouettes, and social adjustments of
relationship in the smashed wrist-watch scene in Mikey and Nicky, or
the tumultuous, continuously morphing emotional reconfigurations in the
scene between Nicky and his wife is to find an exhilarating dramatic analogue
to the ideal that Whitman articulated in Democratic Vistasof
variety and freedomÖ . [and] full play for human nature to expand
itself in numberless and even conflicting directions. It is important
to emphasize, however, that Whitman's (and the pragmatist's) understanding
of the meaning of variety and freedom is different from the
understanding of those terms most common today. Our era favors an external
definition (construing variety in terms of racial or sexual
diversity, and freedom in terms of social, political, and
economic possibility) but, as Whitman's own poetry demonstrates, the most
glorious manifestation of full play for human nature to expand itself
is the power of individual consciousness to elude containment or
prediction. The forms of freedom (or enslavement) presented in A Woman
Under the Influence, Faces, or Mikey and Nicky are not
political, sociological, or ideological, but imaginative and emotionalfreedom
not as a position to be attained and held, but as a capacity of movement
that leaves all fixed positions behind, including the position we customarily
call character.
Self-creating expression
Identity becomes mercurial,
watery, flame-like. Rather than being nailed down to an underpinning,
enduring state of subjectivity, identity is allowed to reconfigure itself
in a shifting series of movements and counter-movements. The self can
reform itself as it goes along, turning on itself to critique itself,
altering its tones as it moves through experience. Characters can change
their minds, break their own patterns, and swerve away from their own
past tones, moods, styles. They can present a sequence of behaviors that
won't necessarily snap into focus. They can be surprisingor
mysterious (with real mystery, not mystification introduced to stoke up
the suspense).
It is important to absorb the
difference between the pragmatic appreciation of character as not being
reducible to character and the critical praise lavished on
Norman Bates and other Hollywood depictions because of the alleged complexity
of their having multiple personalities. Norman seems complex
because he combines personal styles and characteristics that are usually
kept separate (maleness and femaleness; adulthood and childlikeness; heterosexuality
and homosexuality; nurturing and threatening behavior; cleanliness and
butchery; cunning and timidity). But, as that list indicates, he is still
constructed out of formulas for selfhood. Norman's dramatic cross-dressing
actually affirms his dependence on conventional categories of selfhood.
(What else are qualities like maleness and femaleness, heterosexuality
and homosexuality, adulthood and childlikeness but paint-by-numbers conceptions
of personality?) Norman is the product of a recipe that combines ingredients
that are usually not mixed together, but a recipe nonetheless. Compare
him with Mabel Longhetti. Mabel is not a quick-change artist who jumps
from one received style or tone to another, but a true creative artist
of her identity, free from indebtedness to all prefabricated roles, tones,
relationships. To watch Mabel, Chet, Jeannnie, Myrtle, Seymour, and Sarah
Lawson (or Elaine May's Mikey and Nicky) is to watch identities and interactions
with others that are exhilaratingly, even a little scarily, undefined.
The pragmatic understanding
of identity is genuinely non-foundational. There is no Mabelno
stable core of subjectivityunderneath or prior to her particular expressions
of herself. There is no self, no pre-defined bundle of subjectivity
separate from and underpinning its shifting manifestations. Consciousness
does not precede expression. As William James argued in Does Consciousness
Exist?in this understanding of experience, consciousness does
not exist as an anterior, defining state. There is only expressionmutating,
unpredictable, and endlessly creative expression. The most interesting
pragmatic characters are genuinely open-ended. Their identities are never
formulated, never finished, ever in process, which is why the best way
to describe these figures is to replace our ordinary conception of selfhood
as a state of being with an appreciation of identity as the tracks left
behind by a continuously adjusted path of doing.
Acting up on screen
It should not be surprising
that pragmatic works encourage a different kind of acting from essentialist
movies. Traditional American film acting, having developed hand in glove
with the idealist forms of presentation favored by Hollywood film, asks
the actor to base his character on an originating, controlling subjective
state. The actor works from the inside outadding accents, manners, and
gestures almost as an afterthought and as secondary to the creation of
the deeper reality. The character's states of feeling and awareness comprise
an invisible underpinning for all of his surface expressions, and the
actor's job in performance is to stay in touch with this essential center
of consciousness. The outcome, at its best, is the inwardness and intensity
of the classic Method acting of Montgomery Clift, Marlon Brando, and James
Dean.
Because it is grounded in states
of individual consciousness, this acting is inevitably individualistic.
Whatever their other strengths, the major American film actorsfrom Dean,
Clift, and Brando in the past, to Jack Nicholson, Robert DeNiro, Harvey
Keitel, Meryl Streep, Christopher Walken, Crispen Glover, and Nicholas
Cage more recentlyperform their work essentially alone. No matter how
many others are present on camera with them, they are seldom genuinely
responsive to anyone else. Jack Nicholson steals every scene he is in,
controlling the beats, mugging, clowning, doing star turns.
Harvey Keitel's dialogue passages are delivered as if they were monologues.
Christopher Walken, Nicholas Cage, and Crispin Glover communicate the
effect of being tuned into their own private frequencies no one else can
hear, wrestling personal demons. These figures are among the greatest
living American actors, and they do lots of interesting things, but it
is telling that they do them more or less on their ownby themselves
and to themselves, reaching into their own private reservoirs of feeling
and knowledge.
Pragmatic acting goes in the
opposite direction. Since it imagines selfhood not in terms of the creation
and maintenance of states of private subjectivity, but as a flowing, dynamic
process of responsiveness, it says that rather than burrowing ever deeper
into himself, the actor's job is to reach ever more outward to others.
While Method acting creates isolated (and frequently noncommunicating)
packets of inviolable selfhood, the pragmatist says that, like Mabel Longhetti,
Chet, Jeannie, or Sarah, we share our selves with others and create ourselves
in negotiation with them. The goal is to look, listen, and respond freely
and openly to those around you. Identity is not the result of maintaining
the integrity of a deep private self; but is created, adjusted, and recreated
in social interaction. Creativity is not the product of a deep inward
consistency, but of nimble, flexible responsiveness. We renegotiate our
identities with every beat of every interaction. We bring ourselves into
fullest and richest being in our relationships with others. To act is
to interact.
Experiential swerves and interruptions
What is true of personal identity
in nonfoundational works is true of all aspects of experience: It is opened-up.
The pragmatist does not believe experience can be mapped in terms of progress
along a unidirectional narrative path. The classic screenwriting formula
that a narrative is a character with a goal, confronted with an
obstacle is a recipe for an essentialist film only. In the pragmatic
view, the reduction of life to goals and obstacles, plans and frustrations
is a hopeless reduction of the actual complexity of lived experience.
Idealist works unify experience by suggesting that characters can pursue
a more or less monotonic narrative trajectory through it; pragmatic works
celebrate the diversity and heterogeneity of experience by allowing continuous
narrative switch-backs, side-tracks, and divagations.
I am speaking metaphorically,
of course, but in fact many visionary and pragmatic films actually present
experience in terms of similar spatial metaphors. Experience in Psycho,
Rear Window, and North by Northwest is generally mapped in
straight lines, while experience in Mikey and Nicky, The Rules
of the Game, The Killing of a Chinese Bookie, and De Sica's
Bicycle Thief (another classic of pragmatic understanding) zigzags
not only imaginatively, but spatially. With a dreamlike consistency, Hitchcock's
work defines life in terms of straight-ahead movements through space.
Like Marion Crane driving in the rain or Arbogast and Lila making their
way up the steps of the Bates mansion, the main characters (and the camera)
relentlessly move forwardoptically and imaginatively pressuring and
forcing encounters with whatever is in front of them. The clear implication
is that we understand the world by striking, probing, pushing until we
break through the delusive surface and reach a secret inner truth (which,
in Hitchcock's work, is often figured as the interior room in a house
or an underground plot or cellar). In contrast, the Renoir, Cassavetes,
May, and De Sica films suggest that there is no inside, no underneath,
no beyond to get to, and no secret to uncover. There is no hidden basement
of the imagination to work our way down into, but only delightful, dismaying,
distracting surfaces to negotiatefrequently figured in these works as
a maze of passages, hallways, or streets angling off in every direction.
At the same time, even pragmatic
filmmakers recognize that the visionary impulse makes a powerful appeal
to our imaginations. As James might have put it, we want points of anchorage
that will resolve the turbulence and turbidness of surface expressions.
No matter how much experience teaches us otherwise, we want to believe
in the possibility of secrets and discoveries that will ultimately clarify
the opacity of experience. Pragmatic works often include characters on
essentialist questsfigures who attempt to maintain fixed trajectories
through experience, who search for resolving, deep insights
and visionary unifications of the randomness and sprawl of experienceeven
as the films simultaneously frustrate their designs for living. Jurieu,
Cosmo, Mikey, and Antonio attempt to take express-trains to get
from point A to B without having to make annoying stops en route,
but Renoir, Cassavetes, May, and De Sica narratively derail their progress
over and over again. Even as these characters attempt to pursue serious,
goal-oriented missions, their films spin them out along weird, semi-comic
narrative curlicues and tangentsexposing them to fascinating distractions,
tantalizingly leading them down emotional blind alleys, forcing unexpected
reversals of course, and bizarre circlings that as often as not land them
back were they started. While Hitchcock narratively rewards Lila's, Roger's,
Scotty's, and L. B. Jeffries' single-minded purposefulness, Renoir, De
Sica, Cassavetes, and May give Jurieu, Antonio, Cosmo, and Mikey an education
in eccentricity and excursiveness.
The spatial differences between
the two kinds of films are echoed by the temporal differences. The essentialist
narrative is almost always organized around a problem-solving structure
in which earlier scenes ask questions or pose problems which subsequent
scenes then answer or resolve. Time is teleological: earlier events inexorably
lead to later ones and progressively build on them. The narrative is pointed:
it is organized as a series of ever more dramatically resonant confrontations,
climaxes, and resolutions. The pragmatic work breaks away from the tradition
of the well made narrative temporally as much as it does spatially.
It educates its characters and viewers to the limits of cause-and-effect
understandings of experience. It may allow time to pass and nothing apparently
to happen. Characters may get nowhere (from the perspective
of the essentialist narrative) for entire scenes or may even seem to go
backward in terms of their narrative progress. The narrative may be punctuated
by a series delays, hesitations, and pauses. Antonio goes off to a fortune
teller and has to stand in line and listen to other fortunes being told;
he follows a man into a soup kitchen and, before he can have a conversation
with him, has to wait while he gets a shave and is forced to sit through
part of a church service.
John Lennon wrote that life
is what happens when you are making other plans, and as Bicycle Thief
dazzlingly demonstrates, everything that makes life most fascinating is
the result of unexpected glances and movements at a physical right-angle
to where we thought we were headed, at an imaginative angle to our intentions,
goals, and focuses. When Lila works her way into an upstairs bedroom in
the Bates mansion, she is getting ever closer to the truth; when Antonio
does the same thing, he is only pursuing one more dead end. There is nothing
under the bed, no secret to be revealed. He encounters nothing but distractions,
diversions, interruptions, and otherness that won't yield to the pressure
of his own needs and desires. The difference is the difference between
thinking of life as a series of problems to be solved or as experiences
to be undergone. In James' useful term, teleology gives way to process-orientation.
Narrative pluralism
While the essentialist film
tends to be centripetal, accumulative, and progressivespiraling inward
from unimportant characters to important ones, from the unknown to the
known, progressing from the partial to the complete view, from a provisional
understanding to a final one, ever more tightly and revealingly focusing
on a central figure, event, or object (be it Rosebud, a Monolith, a bell
tower, or a mysterious house on a hill), the pragmatic film tends to be
centrifugal, sequential, and digressivemoving away from past positions,
abandoning previously gained ground, spinning off in new directions. Its
law is not ever-tighter focus, but ever-expanding circulation.
The films I have mentioned
by Renoir, De Sica, May, and Cassavetes create the impression that the
narrative contains a host of alternative narratives embedded within it.
When Antonio goes into the police station, when the vehicle announcing
when the soccer game zooms by, when the young lovers kiss in the background,
or when the woman across the courtyard from the bedroom closes the shutters,
we are allowed to glimpse bits and pieces of other stories that, although
they don't quite make it into the main story, seem just as likely prospects
for development. It is as if at any moment, in any scene, the film could
go off in a whole other direction with other characters. The narrative
road is constantly forking with roads taken and not taken (the literal
metaphor for the characters' encounters with experience in both Bicycle
Thieves and Mikey and Nicky).
Given the plurality of stories,
perspectives, truths available in this stylistic universe, the only thing
to do is to keep circulating. No one view can ever be complete or final.
One remembers William James' evocative appropriation of George Eliot's
metaphor of life as a process of swimming through a dark, muddy ocean
in The Meaning of Truth:
The fundamental fact about
our experience is that it is a process of change. For the trower
at any moment, truth, like the visible area round a man walking in a fog,
or what George Eliot calls the wall of dark seen by small fishes'
eyes that pierce a span in the wide Ocean, is an objective field
which the next moment enlarges and of which it is the critic, and which
then either suffers alteration of is continued unchangedÖ. Owing to the
fact that all experience is a process, no point of view can ever be the
last one. Every one is insufficient and off its balance and responsible
to later points of view than itself.
Living in a loose universe
In essentialist films, the
plot and the characters' goals function as a kind of map to keep viewers
and characters on the right interpretive road. They keep us informed about
what to pay attention to, and limit what it may mean. They indicate how
far we and they have come on our journey and suggest how far there is
to go before the narrative destination will be reached. The pragmatic
film denies the viewer such a straight and narrow path through experience.
In its emotional and intellectual zigzags, it resembles the mosaic universe
described by James in A World of Pure Experience:
In actual mosaics the pieces
are held together by their bedding, for which bedding the Substances,
transcendental Egos, or Absolutes of other philosophies may be taken to
stand. In radical empiricism there is no bedding; it is as if the pieces
clung together by their edges, the transitions between them forming their
cement.
James tells us about a
mosaic universe; these films put us in it. They show us what it
looks and feels like to live in a world in which individual experiences
do not take their shape from a narrative beddinga larger,
controlling structure of meaning which limits our interpretation of them.
Characters and scenes are free to reflect their own individual tendencies,
to go off on their own narrative tangents. The pragmatic narrative imagines
a somewhat loose universe, with room for inconsistent, unique, and mutable
expressions. Its allegiance is to honoring the impulse rather than maintaining
the system.
Partial, provisional truths
The implication is that life
is lived minute by minute in the present, and not from the perspective
of eternity, and that if we would apprehend its truths, we must become
present-minded and learn to live in the present. There is something unavoidably
incomplete about the effect of pragmatic style. Less than eventuating
in a final, conclusive understanding, it is given to opening up possibilities.
Less than leaving you with certainties at its end, it is given to removing
whatever certainties may appear to have existed at its start. Even the
small insights that emerge in the course of a pragmatic work are subject
to be corrected by a subsequent change of perspective. To employ one of
James' characteristic formulations, pragmatic truths are typically of
the form: this, but not quiteÖ, this, but a
little moreÖ, this, but thenÖ. Pragmatic
knowledge is on the move and in processcontinually emerging, decaying,
and being reformulated. It doesn't stand still the way thoughts, symbols,
lighting effects, mood music orchestrations, and essential character traits
do.
Nontotalized style
The preceding should suggest
why pragmatic films avoid generalized stylistic effects like mood music,
atmospheric lighting, symbolic props, or editorializing camera angles,
framings, or blockings. Since they reject totalizing understandings of
experience, pragmatic works decline to employ totalizing stylistic devices.
Pragmatic knowledge is tentative, provisional, and multiple. It doesn't
stand still or yield to summary treatment in the form of symbols, lighting
effects, tendentious framings, or mood music. It dares to be more personal
and less absolute than visionary insights. That is why no one would ever
confuse a single scene in The Killing of a Chinese Bookie with
one in Citizen Kane. The Welles film parades one stylistic summary
after another while the Cassavetes work avoids virtually any generalized
visual or acoustic metaphors, symbols, or stylistic glosses of the experiences
it presents. In James' metaphor, Cassavetes' viewer is asked to negotiate
the individual pieces of an experiential mosaicpieces which
somehow hold together, somehow are joined and coherent, somehow connect
one to the other and form a wholewithout an underpinning, summarizing,
abstract, stylistic bedding.
Yet it is important to emphasize
that pragmatic works don't entirely eliminate overarching narrative systems
of causality and purposefulness. The swatches in the crazy quilt do hang
together. The sequences of experiences in Mikey and Nicky and The
Killing of a Chinese Bookie are not haphazard or random. Narrative
structure in pragmatic works functions the way chromatic structure does
in jazz performanceas something to play with and against, as something
not to be ignored but mastered. The actors, characters, and creators of
pragmatic works move a little independently of the narrative throughline
without entirely leaving it behindlike a ballerina who inserts grace
notes or dances slightly against the musical structure she is immersed
inswerving away from the plot, sidetracking it, temporarily putting
it on hold, yet still in a necessary relation to it. Much of the interest
of films like Faces and Mikey and Nicky, in fact, resides
in the ways both the filmmakers and their characters energetically bounce
off of the narrative and emotional throughlines that to some extent
limit their movements. The pragmatic artist tells us that it is in such
a situation of limited constraint that true creativity becomes possible.
Postmodern variations
That should suggest a fundamental
difference between the pragmatic aesthetic and the postmodern. The rootlessness,
present-mindedness, freedom from historical encumbrance, cultivated superficiality,
and overall looseness of the postmodern stance may make it
seem identical to the pragmatic position, but the differences are crucial.
Films like Mikey and Nicky, Faces, A Woman Under the
Influence, and The Killing of a Chinese Bookie demonstrate
that the pragmatic position involves complexly negotiating the
influences that surround us, not merely reclining into them and gliding
along with them. While the postmodern position is slack and relaxed, the
pragmatic is tense and muscular. While the post-modern position involves
passivity and acceptance, the pragmatic requires power, strength, masteryon
the part of both the artist making the work and the main characters in
it (who frequently function as artistic alter egos). For the pragmatist,
anything that is not mastery is misery. As Emerson and William James never
tired of repeating (and as the performances of figures like Mabel Longhetti
and Chet in Cassavetes' work demonstrate), the pragmatic stance involves
unceasing expressive workthe labor of making meanings in a world
in which past compositions are constantly decomposing and new meaning-making
meets with unending resistance. The postmodern position represents an
entirely easier, more playful, and less serious stylistic surfboard ride.
The postmodernist goes with the flow, while the pragmatist tacks and trims
and sails upon and against it, turning its very resistance into a countervailing
form of power.
It is equally important to
emphasize the chasm separating the pragmatic position from the skepticism
and suspension of value judgments implicit in postmodern understandings.
In the open-endedness and sprawl of their narratives, in their rejection
of monotonic paths through experience and their relish of different angles
of vision, pragmatic artists are not arguing (in the postmodernist vein)
that there are no truths, but that there are many. The pragmatist rejects
truth to give us truthsunitary truth replaced by plural truths; present
truth leaving past truth behind; your truth compared with my truth; but
that is entirely different from jettisoning the concept of truth altogether
or relativizing it to the point that value judgment becomes impossible.
If the pragmatist is convinced that no truth can be final, and that no
one perspective can be definitive, the point is not to suspend judgment
and make everything equal, but to enrich and complicate value judgment
so that it will be better informed. The point of pragmatic circulation
through many different perspectives is that the exposure to many can inform
the understanding of each. To enter into the kaleidoscopic perspectivism
of Faces and the relentless multiple-mindedness of A Woman Under
the Influence is not to be set adrift in a world where everyone and
every point of view is equally acceptable, but rather to be put in a better
position to judge whether (as William James puts it in Pragmatism
and Humanism) the fluxÖrises or falls in value as a
result of each characters' transformation of it. We can all the more clearly
perceive Dr. Zepp's and Nick's and Richard's and Maria's individual limitations
because we have had the opportunity to circulate through so many different
ways of being and knowing, each of which has been respected and honored
it itself. In fact, it is only when the pieces of the experiential mosaic
are really allowed to assume their own independent inclinations, are allowed
to be completely and utterly themselves, that we can fairly assess the
true value of each piece.
An art of the ordinary
A common objection to many
of the works I have singled out for praise is that they are raw, rough,
unpolished, or downright ugly. Because they deny themselves stylistic
clarifications, Cassavetes' and May's works emphatically lack the visual
and acoustic gorgeousness of Welles' or Kubrick's. The Killing of a
Chinese Bookie has none of the beauty shots, luxurious
musical orchestrations, or symbolic sets and props that Citizen Kane
employs. Cassavetes' characters and settings don't lend themselves to
metaphorical summarization. Their uniqueness (bodies, faces, and voices
are particularized; locations are not generic) defies generalization;
their physicality (doors stick and objects scrape, clothing doesn't always
fit; interactions are not chiefly mental) resists metaphoric derealization.
While visionary filmmakers project characters and viewers into a realm
of conceptual clarity and stylistic purity disconnected from the mess
and clutter of the world that exists outside of the movie theater, pragmatic
artists offer truths that emphatically do not rise above spatial particularities
and temporal contingencies.
The beauties in most of the
classics of American idealist filmfrom Sternberg and Welles to Hitchcock,
Kubrick, Spielberg, and Lynchare fundamentally unworldly. They originate
in the human imagination and have their ultimate form of expression in
stylistic arrangements unique to works of art: in effects of light and
sound, in narrative parallelisms and contrasts, in virtuosities of formal
presentation. The beauties in Renoir's, Leigh's, Cassavetes', and May's
work, in contrast, are practical. They represent acts of awareness,
responsiveness, and social expression that it is actually possible to
live. The pragmatic artist sees the world, not the work
of art, as the place where the most important and valuable meanings are
and must be made. Rather than establishing a special, enchanted realm
of imaginative transformations somewhere beyond ordinary experience, pragmatic
art lets the forms and energies of everyday life reach into the work,
and those of the work reach into the world.
Every visual and acoustic sublimity
in Citizen Kane, The Trial, Vertigo, Rear Window,
2001, Apocalypse Now, Full Metal Jacket, or LA
Confidential tells us how uninterested these directors are in the
struggles, strivings, and undergoings of ordinary, nonvisionary life as
it is lived outside the movie theater. Whatever their other merits, these
works are world-denying, world-renouncing, world-fleeing. The pragmatic
artist argues that we do not have to rise above the mess, mutability,
and mundanity of everyday life to be profoundly and meaningfully creative.
Renoir's, Leigh's, Cassavetes', and May's characters participate in the
glorious dream that animates all pragmatic art and philosophy: the faith
that our supreme acts of creativity do not have to be relegated to a world
elsewhere of imagination (or artistic style), but that we can be
artists of everyday lifeexpressing ourselves in our everyday personalities,
words, gestures, and interactions with others.
The pragmatic work returns
us to the ideal of artistic realization that Emerson invoked
at the end of Experience when he wrote that the true
romance which the world seeks to realize, will be the transformation of
genius into practical power. Though this vision of an art of the
ordinary represents an admittedly minority position, it is a current energizing
the great tradition of American expressionfrom Emerson and Hawthorne,
to Eakins, Sargent, Henry and William James, and Dewey in this century
(where it finds its most extended expression in Art as Experience).
The following passage from Emerson's Art must stand for all:
Beauty must come back to the
useful arts and the distinction between the fine and useful arts be forgotten.
If history were truly told, if life were nobly spent, it would no longer
be easy or possible to distinguish the one from the other. In nature,
all is useful, all is beautiful.Ö Art has not yet come to its maturity.
. . if it is not practical and moral.Ö There is higher work for art than
the arts.Ö Nothing less than the creation of man and nature is its end.
What would it mean to take
this passage seriouslynot as a figure of speech or an imaginative extravagance,
but as a practical program of action? What would it mean for art to have
not the creation of works, but the creation of man as its
purpose? Pragmatic filmmakers show us one possible answer.
Knowledge that won't formulate
My final point is that the
pragmatic way of knowing is not one more system of knowledge, but in fact
a rejection of all systems. The heart of the pragmatic understanding is
that lived experience overflows all forms of understandingincluding
the forms these works themselves offer. The pragmatic artist accepts the
fact that experience leaks out of all intellectual and stylistic containers.
That is why it would completely misunderstand my argument to interpret
it as implying that filmmakers can simply shift from idealist
forms of expression to pragmatic onesas if there were such
a thing as a pragmatic form that filmmakers could merely pour
their stories into. The pragmatic stance does not provide a recipe to
cook up art to order (say, one in which rough, partial,
personal, or physical forms of expression are
substituted for smooth, totalized, absolute,
or spiritual forms of expression). The pragmatic stance is
the rejection of all recipes and received forms. It is less a formulated
style than evidence of a stylistic breakdown. Pragmatic style is what
is left by the failure of style to suffice. The pragmatic style is what
happens when the artist is sensitive enough to see that his own formulas
will not quite formulatewhen he accepts stylistic failure and
allows himself to fail over and over again. Pragmatic knowledge is less
an alternative to visionary/ideal/essential forms of knowledge, than it
is the final waking up from the dream of such forms. Pragmatic films critique
all conceptual stances, all fixed understandings, all
efforts to possess experience abstractly. They indicate the insufficiency
of all attempts to control and contain experienceeven their own. That
is why, in the most profound sense, they ultimately bring us back to life.
Dirty truth
It's no wonder most viewers
and critics have not embraced pragmatic forms of knowledge. The pragmatic
viewing experience is far more demanding than the experience of idealist
work. Visionary film gives us quick, summary, shorthand truth; pragmatic
film offers slow, scrawly truth-in-motion. Visionary work gives us smooth,
streamlined, clean knowledge; pragmatic film gives us lumpy, rough, dirty
knowledge. Visionary work offers the prospect of deep, insightful, essential
understanding, while pragmatic film offers mazes of superficial, multivalent,
hazy expressions. The pragmatic display of energy in motion tests both
a viewer's powers to keep up with it and a critic's powers to describe
it. After many years of evolution, our brains have become much better
at grappling with things than movements, and most criticism
has unfortunately internalized essentialist understandings of life and
art, with the result that it is not very good at dealing with the ways
pragmatic works make meanings. We are much better at describing works
that offer us metaphoric or symbolic images than ones that expand
our powers of response; we are much more attentive to stances
than movements, and more interested in systems of relationship
and identity, than in surging, shifting flows of energy. To this
neoclassical understanding of art, masterworks like Mikey and Nicky
and Faces merely seem disorganized or confusing.
Critical difficulty
Living as we do in the shadow
of Plato, accustomed to contemplative knowledge, pragmatic knowledge doesn't
look like knowledge at all to most viewers. It looks like randomness or
sprawl. In fact, it is precisely the brilliance of pragmatic works' nonabstracted,
nonintellectualized presentation of experience, their replacement of states
of thought with acts of perception, their devotion to broken
and incomplete forms of knowledge that most viewers and reviewers
mistake for sloppiness or disorganization. Where the experiences so clearly
won't be fit into old forms of meaning, there may seem to be no meaning
at all. In comparison with the virtuousic stylistic accomplishments of
Citizen Kane and 2001, works like Faces and Mikey
and Nicky look like a mess to the average viewer.
Needless to say, this entire
essay is premised on the belief that it is possible to come to the opposite
conclusion. If we properly understand them, pragmatic films may make us
realize how life-denying the unworldly beauties of Citizen Kane
and 2001 are. They may remind us that when you leave out the imperfection,
the partialness, and the tentativeness of truth, you've left out a lot
of life. You have eliminated most of what makes us human. From the pragmatic
side of the divide, the inhuman perfection of the stylistic arrangements
of idealist works is a sign not of life but death.
It is undeniable that the work
of pragmatic filmmakers has yet to be given its critical due. Even beyond
the reasons I have already cited, there is clearly something about pragmatic
modernism that camouflages its artistic importance (even as it seems that
there is something about idealist modernism that makes it appear artistically
valuable beyond its intrinsic merits). Perhaps it comes down to something
as simple as the prosaicness of pragmatic characters and narratives. Maybe
it's deep within us to want art that is more elegant, more otherworldly,
more imaginatively rich than life. Once we have defined art as being above
and beyond the travails of ordinary experience, pragmatic narratives just
don't seem grand enough to be great art. Pragmatic films, almost without
exception, are stories of ordinary wives and husbands and children living
in middle-class homes in suburban neighborhoods, shopping in the malls,
or holding nine-to-five jobs. But of course my entire argument is that
the ordinariness of their forms and understandings is, in fact, what makes
these films most extraordinary. Pragmatic films imagine art not to be
set in a special place, and artists not to be special figures. They imagine
ordinary people, at least potentially, as being artists of their own lives.
They imagine the average man or woman on the street as having experiences
that almost pass understanding and defy artistic expression.
The deepest lesson these works
teach us is that the supreme creative possibilities of life can be realized
by figures like us in a world like the one we live in. But they also tell
us that to rise to that challenge we must let go of old ways of knowing
and be willing to accept intellectual clutter and emotional mess in our
transactions with reality. We must brave an adventure of insecurity.....
Excerpted from Two
Forms of Cinematic Modernism: Notes Towards a Pragmatic Aesthetic,
in Townsend Ludington (ed.), A Modern Mosaic: Essays on American Modernism,
Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2000.
To read more of Ray Carney's
thoughts on aesthetics, click on any of the other essays in this section,
any of the discussions of Mike Leigh's work in the Mike Leigh section,
or any of the pieces in Carney on Culture or The Independent
Vision.
This page only
contains excerpts and selected passages from Ray Carney's writing. To
obtain the complete text as well as the complete texts of many pieces
that are not included on the web site,
click here.
|